Yesterday evening I finished watching Werner Herzog‘s 2011 documentary Into the Abyss. The story behind the movie is very simple, one a spree of crimes committed by two young men — really, boys. From the New York Times’s review:
In October 2001, in Conroe, Tex., Sandra Stotler, her son Adam and his friend Jeremy Richardson were murdered, apparently because the killers wanted the red Camaro in Ms. Stotler’s garage. About a week later, after a shootout in a shopping center parking lot, two young men were arrested in the case. One, Jason Burkett, received a life sentence. The other, Michael Perry, was sentenced to death.
The bulk of the movie consists of people being very gently interviewed by Herzog: the bereaved survivors of the victims, detached, professional lawmen, the imprisoned perpetrators and people connected with them. For people looking to feel bad about and for humanity there’s abundant material to chew over here. It’s heartbreaking to watch a woman like Lisa Stolter-Balloun talk about what it’s like to try to live her life after her mother and brother were killed or to watch a would-be tough guy like Charles Richardson gazing at the framed picture of his dead baby brother and struggle not to cry on camera. And it’s downright disturbing — and perhaps a little nausea-inducing — to watch Michael Perry trying to face down the existential anxiety of imminent execution with a parade of smiling clichés of religious and therapeutic uplift. One can tell that he’s not quite persuaded by his own story.
What was really raw, though, was watching the interview of Delbert Burkett, the father of Jason Burkett and himself likely to spend the rest of his life in prison. The elder Burkett blames himself for the dark course his son’s life took. He reflects on what he should have done as a father that he didn’t do: if only I had taken my boys to play baseball, if only I had had them raise a steer like I did when I was a boy, if only I had been there to really teach them right from wrong. When Herzog asks Burkett where the really bad choice was made, Burkett remembers that he had a football scholarship to the University of Texas, but he gave that up, dropped out of high school and football and started to do drugs instead, a choice which led him down a path to a life of crime and imprisonment. How could I not have been riveted at that moment, given my own morbid fascination with life-counterfactuals? If you ever want to see a portrait of a man being eaten alive by his own sense of remorse you can watch this but be warned: it is not easy viewing.
Amidst all the suffering there is an odd twist ending. Jason Burkett ends up being married in prison to a generous, pretty young woman named Melyssa whom he meets through correspondence. (I must wonder: do “normal” men have so little to offer these days that an attractive woman like Melyssa prefers to court and marry a convicted murderer, a man incarcerated in a maximum security prison who will not even be eligible for parole until sometime in the 2040s? Answer: probably yes.) Melyssa has made — so it is strongly implied — a very curious arrangement under which some of Jason’s semen has been smuggled out of prison to inseminate her. She is in an advanced stage of pregnancy by the time Herzog interviews her, and she holds up an ultrasound picture of her yet-to-be-born son on her smartphone for the viewers to see. “You can see he gets his strong chin from me,” she says with evident adoration.
I would imagine that 99 of 100 of Herzog’s viewers will be feeling a warm glow of moral satisfaction at this point. After all this suffering, a happy ending of sorts. Against the claustrophobic images of Texas’s death chamber shown only minutes before, an image of hope and new life. All’s right with the world, after all. This might even be Herzog’s own reading of his documentary. It is the surface that everyone sees, thus the exoteric reading.
And yet I cannot avoid a different reading, because I haven’t forgotten Delbert Burkett and his own lifetime of regret. Given the world as it is, the suffering we have seen, the knowledge that terrible things happen to people like they have happened to most of the interviewees in this movie, given the knowledge that people will almost inevitably make bad choices, how can we justify bringing the innocent child shown on Melyssa Burkett’s smartphone screen into the world. Even the suffering is not a certainty, it is surely a risk. How can we justify materializing the risk.
Perhaps it would be best if I treated my reading of the movie as an esoteric one. I’m sure it’s one that’s upsetting for most people. But I’ve always had a problem staying away from keyboards.
Interesting. I find the “how can we justify” question very confusing, because of ambiguity in the connection between “we” and the decision. I suspect you mean, in an abstract philosophical sense, “how may the decision be justified” or “is it possible to justify” or the stronger claim “it cannot be justified” — but all of these are ways of obscuring what in practicality are the only moral agents connected with the question: Melyssa, Jason, and perhaps the person who helped smuggle the baby batter, depending on the mental state associated with their connivance.
The only question that matters, really, is “how can Melyssa justify the decision?” Given the implication that she can’t — which is another way of saying: “given the antinatalist arguments you’ve expounded previously in this space” — I can’t quite tell whether this is just another well-chosen rhetorical framework for emphasizing those arguments, or whether you are in fact using the “how can we” framing to make the additional argument that a moral agency other than Melyssa (the state, religion, social pressure, Twitter trolls, you and me and a bottle of vodka, I dunno) ought to have input into the decision and and bears at least some of the responsibility for justifying it.
The rude anarchist in me wants to say “Shut up, it’s none of our business, Melyssa is the one who makes this call and she already made it, or more likely has never been exposed to the antinatalist argument and sees no need to justify anything.” And if you were seriously arguing that anybody but Melyssa is responsible for justifying her pregnancies, I think I would indeed respond with a politer version of that. Which is pretty much how I respond to all sorts of arguments that favor social intervention over individual choice in pursuit of utility maximizations.
But I suspect you’re really just making a “this decision is impossible to justify” claim while trying not to be a dick by pointing the finger at Mylissa when you say it. Which is nice of you, but took a lot of unpacking.
My own opinion is that in a world with some joy and a lot of evil, both quite randomly and unevenly distributed, I find myself quite unwilling to second-guess decisions that preference the quest for joy over the likelihood of misery. In the aggregate your arguments carry quite a bit of force, but I don’t think they can reliably predict outcomes for individuals. And letting parents make “best interests of the child” decisions is pretty fundamental to our notions of right living, not because parents do a good job but because we’ve yet to identify any power on earth that reliably does a better one. So my bottom line is that “we” aren’t in the decision loop and Mylissa, who is, is under no moral imperative to justify it — she’s like a lottery player going for the only shot she’ll ever have at a life-changing win, and we’re the mathematicians in this analogy shaking our heads and being pretty damned certain we know better. Sure, it will most likely come to naught but tears, but it’s the only game in town and there’s no more individual decision than whether or not to play.
Pity that the child-to-be can’t somehow weigh in on the decision as to whether or not to leave the blessed calm of nonexistence.
Have we evidence to determine whether it’s not instead a screaming void of chaos?
OK, now, I admit, I’m being oppositional for the reflexive sport of the thing.
Speaking only for myself, mind you, I don’t remember any screaming void of chaos. All the bad stuff I can recall seems have happened after being born.
Good point. On the other hand, people I trust tell me about all sorts of things that happened to me before the age of three that I don’t remember either. And there’s some skin missing from the tip of my dick to back up at least one of those stories. So that’s an existence proof of the unreliability of memory as a guide here.
Just to make it completely clear that I’m arguing just to hear my head roar: I consider it overwhelmingly likely that there’s no experiential component to nonexistence. It’s a niggle when I object to characterizations like “calm” for that lack of experience and sensation; I don’t think “calm” makes any more sense than “screaming chaos” to describe something that isn’t anything. But it’s a niggle precisely because a lack of any experience or sensation — whether it’s “calm” or not — is something one might fairly prefer to experiences and sensations of living.